Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Difference between revisions of "Primitive recursive function"

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
m (tex encoded by computer)
m (Undo revision 48286 by Ulf Rehmann (talk))
Tag: Undo
Line 1: Line 1:
<!--
 
p0746101.png
 
$#A+1 = 47 n = 0
 
$#C+1 = 47 : ~/encyclopedia/old_files/data/P074/P.0704610 Primitive recursive function
 
Automatically converted into TeX, above some diagnostics.
 
Please remove this comment and the {{TEX|auto}} line below,
 
if TeX found to be correct.
 
-->
 
 
{{TEX|auto}}
 
{{TEX|done}}
 
 
 
A function from natural numbers to natural numbers which can be obtained from the initial functions
 
A function from natural numbers to natural numbers which can be obtained from the initial functions
  
$$
+
<table class="eq" style="width:100%;"> <tr><td valign="top" style="width:94%;text-align:center;"><img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746101.png" /></td> </tr></table>
s ( x)  = x + 1,\ \
 
o ( x)  = 0,\ \
 
I _ {m}  ^ {n} ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} )  = x _ {m}  $$
 
  
 
by a finite number of the operations of composition and [[Primitive recursion|primitive recursion]].
 
by a finite number of the operations of composition and [[Primitive recursion|primitive recursion]].
  
Since the initial functions are computable and the operators of superposition and primitive recursion preserve computability, the set of all primitive recursive functions is a subclass of the class of all computable functions (cf. [[Computable function|Computable function]]). Every primitive recursive function is specified by a description of its construction from the initial functions (a primitive recursive description); hence the class of primitive recursive functions is countable. Practically all arithmetic functions used in mathematics for some concrete reason are primitive recursive functions; e.g. $  x + y $,  
+
Since the initial functions are computable and the operators of superposition and primitive recursion preserve computability, the set of all primitive recursive functions is a subclass of the class of all computable functions (cf. [[Computable function|Computable function]]). Every primitive recursive function is specified by a description of its construction from the initial functions (a primitive recursive description); hence the class of primitive recursive functions is countable. Practically all arithmetic functions used in mathematics for some concrete reason are primitive recursive functions; e.g. <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746102.png" />, <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746103.png" />, <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746104.png" />, <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746105.png" />, <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746106.png" /> (the remainder from division of <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746107.png" /> by <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746108.png" />), <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p0746109.png" /> (the prime number with index <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461010.png" />), etc.
$  x \cdot y $,  
 
$  x  ^ {y} $,  
 
$  \mathop{\rm sign} ( x) $,  
 
$  [ x/y] $(
 
the remainder from division of $  x $
 
by $  y $),  
 
$  \pi ( x) $(
 
the prime number with index $  x $),  
 
etc.
 
  
A relation $  P ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $
+
A relation <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461011.png" /> on natural numbers is called a primitive recursive relation if the function <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461012.png" />, equal to 1 if <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461013.png" /> is true and 0 if <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461014.png" /> is false, is primitive recursive. One says that the relation <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461015.png" /> has been obtained from a relation <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461016.png" /> by means of a bounded quantifier if
on natural numbers is called a primitive recursive relation if the function $  g ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $,  
 
equal to 1 if $  P ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $
 
is true and 0 if $  P ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $
 
is false, is primitive recursive. One says that the relation $  P ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , z) $
 
has been obtained from a relation $  Q ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , y, z) $
 
by means of a bounded quantifier if
 
  
$$
+
<table class="eq" style="width:100%;"> <tr><td valign="top" style="width:94%;text-align:center;"><img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461017.png" /></td> </tr></table>
P ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , z)  \iff \
 
\forall y  ( y \leq  z \Rightarrow Q
 
( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , y, z))
 
$$
 
  
 
or
 
or
  
$$
+
<table class="eq" style="width:100%;"> <tr><td valign="top" style="width:94%;text-align:center;"><img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461018.png" /></td> </tr></table>
P ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , z)  \iff \
 
\exists y  ( y \leq  z \& Q
 
( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , y, z)).
 
$$
 
  
 
The class of primitive recursive relations is closed under the application of logical connectives (including negation) and bounded quantifiers.
 
The class of primitive recursive relations is closed under the application of logical connectives (including negation) and bounded quantifiers.
  
Suppose that $  f _ {1} \dots f _ {s + 1 }  $
+
Suppose that <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461019.png" /> are <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461020.png" />-place primitive recursive functions, and let <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461021.png" /> be primitive recursive relations such that for any set of argument values at most one of them is true. Then the function
are $  n $-
 
place primitive recursive functions, and let $  P _ {1} \dots P _ {s} $
 
be primitive recursive relations such that for any set of argument values at most one of them is true. Then the function
 
  
$$ \tag{* }
+
<table class="eq" style="width:100%;"> <tr><td valign="top" style="width:94%;text-align:center;"><img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461022.png" /></td> <td valign="top" style="width:5%;text-align:right;">(*)</td></tr></table>
f ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) = \
 
\left \{
 
  
 
is primitive recursive.
 
is primitive recursive.
  
One says that the function $  f ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , z) $
+
One says that the function <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461023.png" /> has been obtained from an everywhere-defined function <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461024.png" /> by means of the bounded minimization operator if <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461025.png" /> is equal to the minimal <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461026.png" /> such that <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461027.png" /> and <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461028.png" />, and is equal to <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461029.png" /> otherwise. The class of primitive recursive functions is closed under bounded minimization operators.
has been obtained from an everywhere-defined function $  g ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , y, z) $
 
by means of the bounded minimization operator if $  f ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , z) $
 
is equal to the minimal $  y $
 
such that $  y \leq  z $
 
and $  g ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} , y, z) = 0 $,  
 
and is equal to $  z + 1 $
 
otherwise. The class of primitive recursive functions is closed under bounded minimization operators.
 
  
A function $  \Phi ( y, x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $
+
A function <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461030.png" /> is called universal for the class of <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461031.png" />-place primitive recursive functions if for each such function <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461032.png" /> there is a natural number <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461033.png" /> such that
is called universal for the class of $  n $-
 
place primitive recursive functions if for each such function $  f ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $
 
there is a natural number $  k $
 
such that
 
  
$$
+
<table class="eq" style="width:100%;"> <tr><td valign="top" style="width:94%;text-align:center;"><img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461034.png" /></td> </tr></table>
f ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} )  = \
 
\Phi ( k, x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ).
 
$$
 
  
There exists a universal function for every $  n \geq  1 $,  
+
There exists a universal function for every <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461035.png" />, but it need not be primitive recursive.
but it need not be primitive recursive.
 
  
Every recursively enumerable set is the range of values of a primitive recursive function; every recursively enumerable relation $  R ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $
+
Every recursively enumerable set is the range of values of a primitive recursive function; every recursively enumerable relation <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461036.png" /> can be represented as <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461037.png" />, where <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461038.png" /> is a primitive recursive relation. Every primitive recursive function can be represented in formal arithmetic (cf. [[Arithmetic, formal|Arithmetic, formal]]); i.e. for each primitive recursive function <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461039.png" /> there is an arithmetical formula <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461040.png" /> such that for all natural numbers <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461041.png" />, the formula <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461042.png" /> is derivable in formal arithmetic if <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461043.png" />, while <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461044.png" /> is derivable if <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461045.png" />. (Here <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461046.png" /> are arithmetical terms reflecting the natural numbers <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/p/p074/p074610/p07461047.png" /> in formal arithmetic.) This fact takes a central position in the proof of the incompleteness of formal arithmetic (cf. [[#References|[4]]]).
can be represented as $  \exists y  A ( y, x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $,  
 
where $  A $
 
is a primitive recursive relation. Every primitive recursive function can be represented in formal arithmetic (cf. [[Arithmetic, formal|Arithmetic, formal]]); i.e. for each primitive recursive function $  f ( x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $
 
there is an arithmetical formula $  F ( y, x _ {1} \dots x _ {n} ) $
 
such that for all natural numbers $  k _ {1} \dots k _ {n} , m $,
 
the formula $  F ( \overline{m}\; , \overline{k}\; _ {1} \dots \overline{k}\; _ {n} ) $
 
is derivable in formal arithmetic if $  f ( k _ {1} \dots k _ {n} ) = m $,  
 
while $  \neg F ( \overline{m}\; , \overline{k}\; _ {1} \dots \overline{k}\; _ {n} ) $
 
is derivable if $  f ( k _ {1} \dots k _ {n} ) \neq m $.  
 
(Here $  \overline{k}\; _ {1} \dots \overline{k}\; _ {n} , \overline{m}\; $
 
are arithmetical terms reflecting the natural numbers $  k _ {1} \dots k _ {n} , m $
 
in formal arithmetic.) This fact takes a central position in the proof of the incompleteness of formal arithmetic (cf. [[#References|[4]]]).
 
  
 
====References====
 
====References====
 
<table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top">  V.A. Uspenskii,  "Leçons sur les fonctions calculables" , Hermann  (1966)  (Translated from Russian)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD> <TD valign="top">  A.I. Mal'tsev,  "Algorithms and recursive functions" , Wolters-Noordhoff  (1970)  (Translated from Russian)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[3]</TD> <TD valign="top">  H. Rogers jr.,  "Theory of recursive functions and effective computability" , McGraw-Hill  (1967)  pp. 164–165</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[4]</TD> <TD valign="top">  E. Mendelson,  "Introduction to mathematical logic" , v. Nostrand  (1964)</TD></TR></table>
 
<table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top">  V.A. Uspenskii,  "Leçons sur les fonctions calculables" , Hermann  (1966)  (Translated from Russian)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD> <TD valign="top">  A.I. Mal'tsev,  "Algorithms and recursive functions" , Wolters-Noordhoff  (1970)  (Translated from Russian)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[3]</TD> <TD valign="top">  H. Rogers jr.,  "Theory of recursive functions and effective computability" , McGraw-Hill  (1967)  pp. 164–165</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[4]</TD> <TD valign="top">  E. Mendelson,  "Introduction to mathematical logic" , v. Nostrand  (1964)</TD></TR></table>
 +
 +
  
 
====Comments====
 
====Comments====

Revision as of 14:52, 7 June 2020

A function from natural numbers to natural numbers which can be obtained from the initial functions

by a finite number of the operations of composition and primitive recursion.

Since the initial functions are computable and the operators of superposition and primitive recursion preserve computability, the set of all primitive recursive functions is a subclass of the class of all computable functions (cf. Computable function). Every primitive recursive function is specified by a description of its construction from the initial functions (a primitive recursive description); hence the class of primitive recursive functions is countable. Practically all arithmetic functions used in mathematics for some concrete reason are primitive recursive functions; e.g. , , , , (the remainder from division of by ), (the prime number with index ), etc.

A relation on natural numbers is called a primitive recursive relation if the function , equal to 1 if is true and 0 if is false, is primitive recursive. One says that the relation has been obtained from a relation by means of a bounded quantifier if

or

The class of primitive recursive relations is closed under the application of logical connectives (including negation) and bounded quantifiers.

Suppose that are -place primitive recursive functions, and let be primitive recursive relations such that for any set of argument values at most one of them is true. Then the function

(*)

is primitive recursive.

One says that the function has been obtained from an everywhere-defined function by means of the bounded minimization operator if is equal to the minimal such that and , and is equal to otherwise. The class of primitive recursive functions is closed under bounded minimization operators.

A function is called universal for the class of -place primitive recursive functions if for each such function there is a natural number such that

There exists a universal function for every , but it need not be primitive recursive.

Every recursively enumerable set is the range of values of a primitive recursive function; every recursively enumerable relation can be represented as , where is a primitive recursive relation. Every primitive recursive function can be represented in formal arithmetic (cf. Arithmetic, formal); i.e. for each primitive recursive function there is an arithmetical formula such that for all natural numbers , the formula is derivable in formal arithmetic if , while is derivable if . (Here are arithmetical terms reflecting the natural numbers in formal arithmetic.) This fact takes a central position in the proof of the incompleteness of formal arithmetic (cf. [4]).

References

[1] V.A. Uspenskii, "Leçons sur les fonctions calculables" , Hermann (1966) (Translated from Russian)
[2] A.I. Mal'tsev, "Algorithms and recursive functions" , Wolters-Noordhoff (1970) (Translated from Russian)
[3] H. Rogers jr., "Theory of recursive functions and effective computability" , McGraw-Hill (1967) pp. 164–165
[4] E. Mendelson, "Introduction to mathematical logic" , v. Nostrand (1964)


Comments

The fact that the function (*) is primitive recursive under the given assumptions is often rephrased as: the class of primitive recursive functions is closed under "definition by cases" .

References

[a1] C. Calude, "Theories of computational complexity" , North-Holland (1988)
How to Cite This Entry:
Primitive recursive function. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Primitive_recursive_function&oldid=49374
This article was adapted from an original article by S.N. Artemov (originator), which appeared in Encyclopedia of Mathematics - ISBN 1402006098. See original article