Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Difference between revisions of "Pascal, Blaise"

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
(Created page with " {| class="wikitable" !Copyright notice <!-- don't remove! --> |- | This article ''Blaise Pascal'' was adapted from an original article by A.W.F. Edwards, which appeared...")
 
m (accents)
 
(7 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 21: Line 21:
 
enumeration.
 
enumeration.
  
Blaise Pascal was born in Clermont, France. In 1631 his father
+
Blaise Pascal was born in Clermont, France. In 1631 his father Etienne Pascal (himself an able mathematician who gave his name to the
Etienne Pascal (himself an able mathematician who gave his name to the
+
'''limaçon'' of Pascal') moved his family to Paris in order to secure his son a better education, and in 1635 was one of
'''lima&ccedil;on'' of Pascal') moved his family to Paris
 
in order to secure his son a better education, and in 1635 was one of
 
 
the founders of Marin Mersenne's 'Academy', the finest exchange of mathematical  
 
the founders of Marin Mersenne's 'Academy', the finest exchange of mathematical  
 
information in Europe at the time. To this informal academy he introduced his  
 
information in Europe at the time. To this informal academy he introduced his  
Line 42: Line 40:
 
In 1654 Pascal returned to mathematics, extending his early work on conics in a  
 
In 1654 Pascal returned to mathematics, extending his early work on conics in a  
 
manuscript which was never printed and which does not now exist, though it was  
 
manuscript which was never printed and which does not now exist, though it was  
seen by Leibniz. In the same year he entered into correspondence with Pierre de
+
seen by Leibniz. In the same year he entered into correspondence with [[Fermat, Pierre de|Pierre de Fermat]] of Toulouse about some problems in calculating the odds  
Fermat (q.v.) of Toulouse about some problems in calculating the odds  
+
in games of chance which led him to write the ''Traité du
in games of chance which led him to write the ''Trait&eacute; du
+
triangle arithmétique, avec quelques autres petits traitez
triangle arithm&eacute;tique, avec quelques autres petits traitez
+
sur la mesme matière'', probably
sur la mesme mati&egrave;re'', probably
 
 
in August of that year. Not published until 1665, this work, and the  
 
in August of that year. Not published until 1665, this work, and the  
 
correspondence  
 
correspondence  
Line 61: Line 58:
 
years to  
 
years to  
 
writing his ''Lettres provinciales'', written in 1656  
 
writing his ''Lettres provinciales'', written in 1656  
and 1657 in defence of Antoine Arnauld, and his ''Pens&eacute;es'',  
+
and 1657 in defence of Antoine Arnauld, and his ''Pensées'',  
drafts for an ''Apologie de la Religion Chr&eacute;tienne'',  
+
drafts for an ''Apologie de la Religion Chrétienne'',  
 
which include his famous 'wager' (see below). In 1658-59 Pascal briefly  
 
which include his famous 'wager' (see below). In 1658-59 Pascal briefly  
 
returned  
 
returned  
to mathematics, writing on the curve known as the cycloid, but his  
+
to mathematics, writing on the curve known as the [[cycloid]], but his  
 
final input into  
 
final input into  
 
the development of probability theory arises through his presumed  
 
the development of probability theory arises through his presumed  
Line 83: Line 80:
 
du Mont.  
 
du Mont.  
  
The ''Trait&eacute; du triangle arithm&eacute;tique'' itself is 36 pages  
+
The ''Traité du triangle arithmétique'' itself is 36 pages  
 
long (setting aside ''quelques autres petits traitez sur  
 
long (setting aside ''quelques autres petits traitez sur  
la mesme mati&egrave;re'') and consists of two parts. The first carries  
+
la mesme matière'') and consists of two parts. The first carries  
 
the title by which the  
 
the title by which the  
 
whole is usually known, in English translation ''A Treatise  
 
whole is usually known, in English translation ''A Treatise  
Line 145: Line 142:
 
The third interpretation is as a ''combinatorial number'', for the
 
The third interpretation is as a ''combinatorial number'', for the
 
number of combinations of $n$ different things taken $r$ at a time,
 
number of combinations of $n$ different things taken $r$ at a time,
$^{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  {} n}$C$_{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  r}$
+
$^{ {} n}$C$_{ r}$
 
is equal to
 
is equal to
 
${ n \choose r}$,
 
${ n \choose r}$,
Line 153: Line 150:
 
novel demonstration of the combinatorial version of the basic  
 
novel demonstration of the combinatorial version of the basic  
 
addition relation  
 
addition relation  
$^{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  n+}$$^{  1}${\fontshape{it}\selectfont C}$_{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  r+1}${}  
+
$${}^{n+ 1}C_{r+1} = {}^{n}C_{r} + {}^{n}{C}_{r+1}$$,  
= $^{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  {} n}$C$_{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  r}${} +
 
$^{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  {} n}${\fontshape{it}\selectfont C}$_{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  r+}$$_{  1}$,  
 
 
for, considering any particular one of the $n+1$ things,  
 
for, considering any particular one of the $n+1$ things,  
$^{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  n}$C$_{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  r}${}
+
${}^{n}C_{r}$  
 
gives the number of combinations that include it and  
 
gives the number of combinations that include it and  
$^{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  n}${\fontshape{it}\selectfont C}$_{\fontshape{it}\selectfont  r+}$$_{  1}${}
+
${}^{n}C_{r+1}$  
 
the number that exclude it.
 
the number that exclude it.
  
Line 191: Line 186:
 
units are each one half, the expectation is $(a + b)$
 
units are each one half, the expectation is $(a + b)$
 
units, which is then the value of the gamble.  
 
units, which is then the value of the gamble.  
In ''Ars conjectandi'' (1713) James Bernoulli (q.v.) called  
+
In ''Ars conjectandi'' (1713) [[Bernoulli, Jakob|James Bernoulli]] called  
 
this "the fundamental principle of the whole art". Pascal has invented the  
 
this "the fundamental principle of the whole art". Pascal has invented the  
 
concept of "expected value", that is the probability of a win multiplied by  
 
concept of "expected value", that is the probability of a win multiplied by  
Line 200: Line 195:
 
expected values in order to find the correct division of the stake-money,  
 
expected values in order to find the correct division of the stake-money,  
 
and thus computes the "value" of each successive throw. In the  
 
and thus computes the "value" of each successive throw. In the  
''Trait&eacute;'' the same idea is more formally expressed,  
+
''Traité'' the same idea is more formally expressed,  
 
and in particular Pascal gives as a principle the value of the expectation  
 
and in particular Pascal gives as a principle the value of the expectation  
 
when the chances are equal. He remarks at one point that "the division has  
 
when the chances are equal. He remarks at one point that "the division has  
Line 206: Line 201:
 
the players have equal chances the question of computing an expectation for  
 
the players have equal chances the question of computing an expectation for  
 
unequal chances does not arise; that extension was first formally made by  
 
unequal chances does not arise; that extension was first formally made by  
Huygens (q.v.) in his ''De ratiociniis in ludo aleae'' of  
+
[[Huygens, Christiaan|Huygens]] in his ''De ratiociniis in ludo aleae'' of  
 
1657. It is known that when Huygens spent July-September 1655 in Paris he  
 
1657. It is known that when Huygens spent July-September 1655 in Paris he  
 
had the opportunity to discuss Pascal's work on probability problems with  
 
had the opportunity to discuss Pascal's work on probability problems with  
Line 242: Line 237:
 
Three further contributions of Pascal to the development of  
 
Three further contributions of Pascal to the development of  
 
probability theory
 
probability theory
may be noted. In ''Pens&eacute;es'' he used his concept
+
may be noted. In ''Pensées'' he used his concept
 
of expectation to argue that one should bet on the existence of God because,  
 
of expectation to argue that one should bet on the existence of God because,  
 
however small the probability of His existence, the value
 
however small the probability of His existence, the value
Line 253: Line 248:
 
probability theory as the first example of a problem about the duration of  
 
probability theory as the first example of a problem about the duration of  
 
play. Finally, he greatly influenced the probability arguments in the  
 
play. Finally, he greatly influenced the probability arguments in the  
{\fontshape{it}\selectfont Port-Royal Logic}, in the last chapter of which  
+
''Port-Royal Logic'', in the last chapter of which  
 
there is a clear understanding of the importance of judging an action not only  
 
there is a clear understanding of the importance of judging an action not only  
 
by the possible gain or loss, but also by the probability of each of these.  
 
by the possible gain or loss, but also by the probability of each of these.  
Line 266: Line 261:
 
|valign="top"|{{Ref|1}}||valign="top"|  Edwards, A.W.F. (1987). ''Pascal's Arithmetical Triangle'', Griffin, London, and Oxford University Press, New York, 2nd ed. 2000, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore. Contains as appendices Pascal and the Problem of Points ''International Statistical Review'', '''50''', 259-266 (1982) and Pascal's Problem: The "Gambler's Ruin", ''International Statistical Review'', '''51''', 73-79 (1983).  
 
|valign="top"|{{Ref|1}}||valign="top"|  Edwards, A.W.F. (1987). ''Pascal's Arithmetical Triangle'', Griffin, London, and Oxford University Press, New York, 2nd ed. 2000, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore. Contains as appendices Pascal and the Problem of Points ''International Statistical Review'', '''50''', 259-266 (1982) and Pascal's Problem: The "Gambler's Ruin", ''International Statistical Review'', '''51''', 73-79 (1983).  
 
|-
 
|-
|valign="top"|{{Ref|2}}||valign="top"|  Mesnard, J. (1970). ''Oeuvres comp&eacute;tes de Blaise Pascal'', deuxi&egrave;me partie volume I: Oeuvres diverses. Decl&eacute;e de Brouwer, Bruges.  
+
|valign="top"|{{Ref|2}}||valign="top"|  Mesnard, J. (1970). ''Oeuvres complètes de Blaise Pascal'', deuxième partie volume I: Oeuvres diverses. Declée de Brouwer, Bruges.  
 
|-
 
|-
|valign="top"|{{Ref|3}}||valign="top"|  Hald, A. (1990)  ''A History of Probability and Statistics  and their Applications before 1750''. Wiley, New York.  
+
|valign="top"|{{Ref|3}}||valign="top"|  Hald, A. (1990)  ''A History of Probability and Statistics  and their Applications before 1750''. Wiley, New York. {{ZBL|0731.01001}}
 
|-
 
|-
|valign="top"|{{Ref|4}}||valign="top"|  Pascal, B. (1955, 1963) ''Great Books of the Western World 33:  The Provincial Letters,  Pens&eacute;es,'' Scientific Treatises, by Blaise Pascal. Encyclopadia Britannica,  Chicago.  Contains the best English translations of the Pascal-Fermat correspondence  and the ''  Trait&eacute; du triangle arithm&eacute;tique''.
+
|valign="top"|{{Ref|4}}||valign="top"|  Pascal, B. (1955, 1963) ''Great Books of the Western World 33:  The Provincial Letters,  Pensées,'' Scientific Treatises, by Blaise Pascal. Encyclopadia Britannica,  Chicago.  Contains the best English translations of the Pascal-Fermat correspondence  and the ''  Traité du triangle arithmétique''.
 
|-
 
|-
 
|}
 
|}
 
 
 
A.W.F. Edwards
 
 
 
<!-- \end{document} -->
 
<!-- \end{document} -->
  
  
 
<references />
 
<references />
 +
 +
Reprinted with permission from
 +
Christopher Charles Heyde and Eugene William Seneta (Editors),
 +
Statisticians of the Centuries, Springer-Verlag Inc., New York, USA.
  
 
[[Category:Statprob]]
 
[[Category:Statprob]]
 
[[Category:Biographical]]
 
[[Category:Biographical]]

Latest revision as of 06:52, 6 March 2024

Copyright notice
This article Blaise Pascal was adapted from an original article by A.W.F. Edwards, which appeared in StatProb: The Encyclopedia Sponsored by Statistics and Probability Societies. The original article ([http://statprob.com/encyclopedia/BlaisePASCAL.html StatProb Source], Local Files: pdf | tex) is copyrighted by the author(s), the article has been donated to Encyclopedia of Mathematics, and its further issues are under Creative Commons Attribution Share-Alike License'. All pages from StatProb are contained in the Category StatProb.

Blaise PASCAL

b. 19 June 1623 - d. 19 August 1662


Summary Pascal introduced the concept of mathematical expectation and used it recursively to obtain a solution to the Problem of Points which was the catalyst that enabled probability theory to develop beyond mere combinatorial enumeration.

Blaise Pascal was born in Clermont, France. In 1631 his father Etienne Pascal (himself an able mathematician who gave his name to the 'limaçon of Pascal') moved his family to Paris in order to secure his son a better education, and in 1635 was one of the founders of Marin Mersenne's 'Academy', the finest exchange of mathematical information in Europe at the time. To this informal academy he introduced his son at the age of fourteen, and Blaise immediately put his new source of knowledge to good use, producing (at the age of sixteen) his Essay pour les coniques, a single printed sheet enunciating Pascal's Theorem, that the opposite sides of a hexagon inscribed in a conic intersect in three collinear points.

At the age of eighteen the younger Pascal turned his attention to constructing a calculating machine (to help his father in his calculations) and within a few years he had built and sold fifty of them. Some still exist. In 1646 he started work on hydrostatics, determining the weight of air experimentally and writing on the vacuum (leading ultimately to the choice of 'Pascal' as the name for the S.I. unit of pressure).

In 1654 Pascal returned to mathematics, extending his early work on conics in a manuscript which was never printed and which does not now exist, though it was seen by Leibniz. In the same year he entered into correspondence with Pierre de Fermat of Toulouse about some problems in calculating the odds in games of chance which led him to write the Traité du triangle arithmétique, avec quelques autres petits traitez sur la mesme matière, probably in August of that year. Not published until 1665, this work, and the correspondence itself which was published in 1679, is the basis of Pascal's reputation in probability theory as the originator of the concept of expectation and its use recursively to solve the 'Problem of Points', as well as the justification for calling the arithmetical triangle 'Pascal's triangle'. His advances, considered to be the foundation of modern probability theory, are described in detail below.

Later in 1654 Pascal underwent a religious experience as a result of which he almost entirely abandoned his scientific work and devoted his remaining years to writing his Lettres provinciales, written in 1656 and 1657 in defence of Antoine Arnauld, and his Pensées, drafts for an Apologie de la Religion Chrétienne, which include his famous 'wager' (see below). In 1658-59 Pascal briefly returned to mathematics, writing on the curve known as the cycloid, but his final input into the development of probability theory arises through his presumed contribution to La logique, ou l'art de penser by Antoine Arnauld and Pierre Nicole, published in 1662. This classic philosophical treatise is often called the Port-Royal Logic through the association of its authors, and Pascal himself, with the Port-Royal Abbey, a centre of the Jansenist movement within the Catholic church, into whose convent Pascal's sister Jacqueline had been received in 1652.

Pascal died in Paris, in good standing with the Church and is buried in the church of St Etienne du Mont.

The Traité du triangle arithmétique itself is 36 pages long (setting aside quelques autres petits traitez sur la mesme matière) and consists of two parts. The first carries the title by which the whole is usually known, in English translation A Treatise on the Arithmetical Triangle, and is an account of the arithmetical triangle as a piece of pure mathematics. The second part Uses of the Arithmetical Triangle consists of four sections: (1)Use in the theory of figurate numbers, (2)Use in the theory of combinations, (3)Use in dividing the stakes in games of chance, (4)Use in finding the powers of binomial expressions.

Pascal opens the first part by defining an unbounded rectangular array like a matrix in which 'The number in each cell is equal to that in the preceding cell in in the same row', and he considers the special case in which the cells of the first row and column each contain 1. Symbolically, he has defined $\{f_{i,j}\}$ where $$f_{i,j} = f_{i-1,j} + f_{i,j-1}, i,j= 2,3,4,..., f_{i,1}= f_{1,j} = 1, i,j = 1,2,3,...$$

The rest of Part I is devoted to a demonstration of nineteen corollaries flowing from this definition, and concludes with a 'problem'. The corollaries include all the common relations among the binomial coefficients (as the entries of the triangle are now universally called), none of which was new. Pascal proves the twelfth corollary, $(j-1)f_{i,j} = if_{i+1,j-1}$ in our notation, by explicit use of mathematical induction. The `problem' is to find $f_{i,j}$ as a function of $i$ and $j$, which Pascal does by applying the twelfth corollary recursively. Part I of the Treatise thus amounts to a systematic development of all the main results then known about the properties of the numbers in the arithmetical triangle.

In Part II Pascal turns to the applications of these numbers. The numbers thus defined have three different interpretations, each of great antiquity (to which he does not, however, refer). The successive rows of the triangle define the figurate numbers which have their roots in Pythagorean arithmetic. Pascal treats these in section (1),

The second interpretation is as binomial numbers, the coefficients of a binomial expansion, which are arrayed in the successive diagonals, their identity with the figurate numbers having been recognized in Persia and China in the eleventh century and in Europe in the sixteenth. The above definition of $f_{i,j}$ is obvious on considering the expansion of both sides of $$(x+y)^n = (x+y) (x+y)^{n-1}.$$ The fact that the coefficient of $x^{r} y^{n-r}$ in the expansion of $(x+y)^n$ may be expressed as $$ \frac{n(n-1)(n-2)...(n-r+1)}{1.2.3...r} = {n \choose r}$$ was known to the Arabs in the thirteenth century and to the Renaissance mathematician Cardano in 1570. It provides a closed form for $f_{i,j}$, with $n = i + j -2$ and $r = i -1$. Pascal treats the binomial interpretation in section (4).

The third interpretation is as a combinatorial number, for the number of combinations of $n$ different things taken $r$ at a time, $^{ {} n}$C$_{ r}$ is equal to ${ n \choose r}$, a result known in India in the ninth century, to Hebrew writers in the fourteenth century, and to Cardano in 1550. Pascal deals with that interpretation in section (2), giving a novel demonstration of the combinatorial version of the basic addition relation $${}^{n+ 1}C_{r+1} = {}^{n}C_{r} + {}^{n}{C}_{r+1}$$, for, considering any particular one of the $n+1$ things, ${}^{n}C_{r}$ gives the number of combinations that include it and ${}^{n}C_{r+1}$ the number that exclude it.

In section (3) Pascal breaks new ground, and this section, taken together with his correspondence with Fermat, is the basis of his reputation as the father of probability theory. The "problem of points" which he discusses, also known simply as the "division problem", involves determining how the total stake should be divided in the event of a game of chance being terminated prematurely. Suppose two players $X$ and $Y$ stake equal money on being the first to win $n$ points in a game in which the winner of each point is decided by the toss of a fair coin. If such a game is interrupted when $X$ still lacks $x$ points and $Y$ lacks $y$, how should the total stake be divided between them? In the middle of the sixteenth century Tartaglia famously concluded "the resolution of such a question is judicial rather than mathematical, so that in whatever way the division is made there will be cause for litigation". A century later, in the summer of 1654, the correct solution was derived by three different arguments during the correspondence between Pascal and Fermat. One of the methods, advanced by Pascal in his letter of July 29, involves computing expectations recursively.

The key development was his understanding that the value of a gamble is equal to its mathematical expectation computed as the average of the values of each of two equally-probable outcomes, and that this precise definition of value lends itself to recursive computation because the value of a gamble that one is certain to win is undoubtedly the total stake itself. Thus if the probabilities of winning $a$ or $b$ units are each one half, the expectation is $(a + b)$ units, which is then the value of the gamble. In Ars conjectandi (1713) James Bernoulli called this "the fundamental principle of the whole art". Pascal has invented the concept of "expected value", that is the probability of a win multiplied by its value, and understood that it is an exact mathematical concept which can be manipulated.

In the letter to Fermat, Pascal develops the recursive argument applied to expected values in order to find the correct division of the stake-money, and thus computes the "value" of each successive throw. In the Traité the same idea is more formally expressed, and in particular Pascal gives as a principle the value of the expectation when the chances are equal. He remarks at one point that "the division has to be proportional to the chances", but in the solution to the problem when the players have equal chances the question of computing an expectation for unequal chances does not arise; that extension was first formally made by Huygens in his De ratiociniis in ludo aleae of 1657. It is known that when Huygens spent July-September 1655 in Paris he had the opportunity to discuss Pascal's work on probability problems with Roberval, and presumably learnt of the concept of mathematical expectation then.

The easiest way to understand how Pascal used expectation and recursion to solve the problem of points is to visualise the event-tree of possible further results. Each bifurcation corresponds to a toss, one branch for $X$ winning it and the other for $Y$, and successive bifurcations must lead eventually to tips corresponding to the whole game being won by either $X$ or $Y$. Considering now the expectation of $X$ (say), each tip can be labelled with his expectation, either $S$ (the total stake) or 0, as the case may be. Applying now Pascal's expectation rule for equal chances, each bifurcation can have an expectation associated with it, working recursively down the tree from the tips to the root, at which point we find the solution to the problem. If $E(x,y)$ be the expectation of player $X$ when he lacks $x$ points and $Y$ lacks $y$, then the recursion is $$ E(x,y) = E(x-1,y) + E(x,y-1).$$

By these methods, and his knowledge of the arithmetical triangle, Pascal was able to demonstrate how the stake should be divided between the players according to the partial sums of the binomial coefficients, a result which he had already obtained by enumeration, for both he and Fermat had realised that the actual game of uncertain length could be embedded in a game of fixed length to which the binomial distribution (as yet undiscovered) could then be applied. Further details of their reasoning may be found in the references below.

Three further contributions of Pascal to the development of probability theory may be noted. In Pensées he used his concept of expectation to argue that one should bet on the existence of God because, however small the probability of His existence, the value of eternal salvation if He does exist is infinite, so that the expected value of assuming that He does exist far exceeds that of assuming that He does not. Subsequent writers have regarded this, "Pascal's wager", as the origin of decision theory. Secondly, in 1656 Pascal posed Fermat a problem which became known as the "gambler's ruin" and which played a central role in the development of probability theory as the first example of a problem about the duration of play. Finally, he greatly influenced the probability arguments in the Port-Royal Logic, in the last chapter of which there is a clear understanding of the importance of judging an action not only by the possible gain or loss, but also by the probability of each of these. One must "consider mathematically the magnitudes when these things are multiplied together". This is the first occasion in which the word `` probability" is used (in French, of course) in its modern sense.


References

[1] Edwards, A.W.F. (1987). Pascal's Arithmetical Triangle, Griffin, London, and Oxford University Press, New York, 2nd ed. 2000, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore. Contains as appendices Pascal and the Problem of Points International Statistical Review, 50, 259-266 (1982) and Pascal's Problem: The "Gambler's Ruin", International Statistical Review, 51, 73-79 (1983).
[2] Mesnard, J. (1970). Oeuvres complètes de Blaise Pascal, deuxième partie volume I: Oeuvres diverses. Declée de Brouwer, Bruges.
[3] Hald, A. (1990) A History of Probability and Statistics and their Applications before 1750. Wiley, New York. Zbl 0731.01001
[4] Pascal, B. (1955, 1963) Great Books of the Western World 33: The Provincial Letters, Pensées, Scientific Treatises, by Blaise Pascal. Encyclopadia Britannica, Chicago. Contains the best English translations of the Pascal-Fermat correspondence and the Traité du triangle arithmétique.



Reprinted with permission from Christopher Charles Heyde and Eugene William Seneta (Editors), Statisticians of the Centuries, Springer-Verlag Inc., New York, USA.

How to Cite This Entry:
Pascal, Blaise. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Pascal,_Blaise&oldid=37963