Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Gödel constructive set

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
The printable version is no longer supported and may have rendering errors. Please update your browser bookmarks and please use the default browser print function instead.

Gödel constructible set, constructible set

A set that arises in the process of constructing sets described below. Let $ X $ be a set and $ R \subseteq X \times X $ a relation on $ X $. Then consider the first-order language $ L(R,X) $ containing (i) a binary predicate symbol $ \underline{R} $ denoting the relation $ R $ and (ii) individual constant symbols denoting the elements of $ X $ (for each $ x \in X $, its corresponding constant symbol is $ \underline{x} $). The statement “the formula $ \phi $ of the language $ L(R,X) $ is valid in the model $ M = (X,R) $” is written as $$ M \models \phi. $$

A set $ Y \subseteq X $ is called “definable” in the model $ M = (X,R) $ (or $ M $-definable) if and only if there exists a formula $ \phi(v) $ of $ L(R,X) $ with one free variable $ v $ such that $$ \forall x \in X: \quad x \in Y \iff M \models \phi(x). $$

Let $ \operatorname{Def}(M) $ denote the set of all $ M $-definable sets. To each ordinal $ \alpha $ is associated the set $ L_{\alpha} $ that is recursively defined by the relation $$ L_{\alpha} = \bigcup_{\beta < \alpha} \operatorname{Def} \left( L_{\beta},\in \!\! |_{L_{\beta}} \right), $$ where $ \in \!\! |_{L_{\beta}} $ denotes the membership relation restricted to $ L_{\beta} $. Hence, it follows that \begin{align} L_{0} & = \varnothing, \\ L_{1} & = \{ \varnothing \}, \\ L_{2} & = \{ \varnothing,\{ \varnothing \} \}, \\ & \vdots \\ L_{\omega} & = \bigcup_{n < \omega} L_{n}, \\ & \vdots \end{align}

A set $ z $ is called “constructible” if and only if there exists an ordinal $ \alpha $ such that $ z \in L_{\alpha} $. The class of all constructible sets is the (Gödel) constructible universe, denoted by $ L $. In 1938, Kurt Gödel defined $ L $ and introduced the following axiom of constructibility: Every set is constructible. On the basis of the axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $, he proved that in $ L $, all axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ hold as well as the axiom of constructibility, and that the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis (“for every ordinal $ \alpha $, one has $ 2^{\aleph_{\alpha}} = \aleph_{\alpha + 1} $”) follow in $ \mathsf{ZF} $ from the axiom of constructibility.

The class $ L $ can also be characterized as the smallest class that is a model of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ and contains all the ordinals; there are other ways of defining $ L $ (see [2][4]). The relation $ z \in L_{\alpha} $ can be expressed by a formula in the language of $ \mathsf{ZF} $, which is moreover of a simple syntactic structure (a so-called $ \Delta_{1}^{\mathsf{ZF}} $, cf. ).

Some results relating to constructible sets. The set of constructible real numbers (cf. Constructive Real Number), that is, the set $ \mathbb{R} \cap L $ (where $ \mathbb{R} $ is the set of all real numbers, viewed as sequences of $ 0 $’s and $ 1 $’s), is a $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $-set (see [5]). It has been shown that the axiom of constructibility implies the existence of a non-Lebesgue-measurable set of real numbers of type $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $ (see [6]), the negation of the Suslin Hypothesis and the non-existence of measurable cardinals (see [2]).

References

[1a] K. Gödel, “The consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum hypothesis”, Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 24 (1938), pp. 556–557.
[1b] K. Gödel, “Consistency proof for the generalized continuum hypothesis”, Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 25 (1939), pp. 220–224.
[2] T.J. Jech, “Lectures in set theory: with particular emphasis on the method of forcing”, Lect. Notes in Math., 217, Springer (1971).
[3] A. Mostowski, “Constructible sets with applications”, North-Holland (1969).
[4] C. Karp, “A proof of the relative consistency of the continuum hypothesis”, J. Crossley (ed.), Sets, models and recursion theory, North-Holland (1967), pp. 1–32.
[5] J.W. Addison, “Some consequences of the axiom of constructibility”, Fund. Math., 46 (1959), pp. 337–357.
[6] P.S. Novikov, “On the non-contradictability of certain propositions of descriptive set theory”, Trudy Mat. Inst. Steklov., 38 (1951), pp. 279–316 (in Russian).
[7] U. Felgner, “Models of $ \mathsf{ZF} $-set theory”, Springer (1971).

Comments

Concerning (the notation) $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $, see Descriptive Set Theory.

As a consequence of Gödel’s findings, if the axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ are non-contradictory, then they remain so after adding the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis. This was the first relative consistency result of any importance for $ \mathsf{ZF} $, to be surpassed only after a quarter of a century in 1963 by Paul Cohen’s method of forcing. By forcing, it is known that $ \mathsf{ZF} $ cannot prove the axiom of constructibility (unless it is contradictory). Most set theorists think that there are no sufficient reasons to believe it to be true. Nevertheless, $ L $ is an important subclass of the set-theoretic universe that is well worth investigating.

New results can be found in [a1], which is also a good introduction to the concept of constructibility. Reference [a2] contains (most of) the material touched upon in the main article.

References

[a1] K.J. Devlin, “Constructibility”, Springer (1984).
[a2] T.J. Jech, “Set theory”, Acad. Press (1978), pp. 523ff (translated from German).
[a3] K. Kunen, “Set theory, an introduction to independence proofs”, North-Holland (1980).
[a4] K. Gödel, “The consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum hypothesis with the axioms of set theory”, Princeton Univ. Press (1940).
[a5] K. Devlin, “Constructibility”, J. Barwise (ed.), Handbook of mathematical logic, North-Holland (1977), pp. 453–490.
How to Cite This Entry:
Gödel constructive set. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=G%C3%B6del_constructive_set&oldid=51317
This article was adapted from an original article by V.N. Grishin (originator), which appeared in Encyclopedia of Mathematics - ISBN 1402006098. See original article