Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Difference between revisions of "Analytic model of a language"

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
(Importing text file)
 
m (tex encoded by computer)
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
<!--
 +
a0123401.png
 +
$#A+1 = 47 n = 0
 +
$#C+1 = 47 : ~/encyclopedia/old_files/data/A012/A.0102340 Analytic model of a language,
 +
Automatically converted into TeX, above some diagnostics.
 +
Please remove this comment and the {{TEX|auto}} line below,
 +
if TeX found to be correct.
 +
-->
 +
 +
{{TEX|auto}}
 +
{{TEX|done}}
 +
 
''analyzing model of a language''
 
''analyzing model of a language''
  
 
A type of mathematical construction used in mathematical linguistics to describe the structure of natural languages. These constructions are used in the formal modelling of basic linguistic categories and of the process of linguistic research itself; in other words, certain sets of  "disordered"  data about the language (or, more exactly, about speech) are used to deduce certain information about the structural mechanism of the language, i.e. about its grammar in the wider sense of this word. The  "functioning"  of such a model does not always have the character of an effective construction, since the set of initial data need not be a constructive object; in principle, this does not render such models inferior.
 
A type of mathematical construction used in mathematical linguistics to describe the structure of natural languages. These constructions are used in the formal modelling of basic linguistic categories and of the process of linguistic research itself; in other words, certain sets of  "disordered"  data about the language (or, more exactly, about speech) are used to deduce certain information about the structural mechanism of the language, i.e. about its grammar in the wider sense of this word. The  "functioning"  of such a model does not always have the character of an effective construction, since the set of initial data need not be a constructive object; in principle, this does not render such models inferior.
  
In the most fully developed analytic models of languages, the set of initial data is usually an object which models a set of grammatical sentences of a natural language, viz. some [[Formal language|formal language]] in a given alphabet (vocabulary) <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123401.png" />. If <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123402.png" /> is a language in the vocabulary <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123403.png" /> and <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123404.png" />, then one says that the string <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123405.png" /> can be substituted by the string <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123406.png" /> with respect to <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123407.png" /> and <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123408.png" />; if each one the strings <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a0123409.png" /> and <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234010.png" /> can be substituted by the other with respect to <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234011.png" /> and <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234012.png" />, then one says that <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234013.png" /> and <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234014.png" /> can be mutually substituted with respect to <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234015.png" /> and <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234016.png" />. The concept of mutual substitutability has a simple linguistic meaning: If <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234017.png" /> is understood to be the set of grammatical sentences of some natural language, the mutually substitutable sets are  "syntactically equivalent"  (i.e. fulfilling the same syntactic functions) word combinations. In particular, if a single-symbol string <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234018.png" /> (in linguistic interpretation: a word) is mutually substitutable with a string <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234019.png" /> of length <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234020.png" />, <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234021.png" /> is a  "potential constituent" , i.e. may be a constituent of the linguistically natural constituent structures of grammatical sentences of this language (cf. [[Syntactic structure|Syntactic structure]]); in such a case the string <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234022.png" /> is called a first rank configuration of the language <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234023.png" /> with resultant <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234024.png" />. Thus, in the English language, the string  "uniformly continuous"  can be regarded as a first rank configuration with resultant  "continuous" . However, first rank configurations do not exhaust all  "potential constituents" ; for example, the word combination  "continuous function"  is not a first rank configuration, since only words such as  "function" ,  "derivative" , etc., can be substituted by it, but it cannot itself be substituted by any of these words ( "fx is a uniformly continuous function"  is a correct statement, but  "fx is a uniform function"  is not). Therefore one introduces the following definition: If <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234025.png" /> is a natural number and if the concept of a rank <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234026.png" /> configuration of the language <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234027.png" /> has been defined for each <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234028.png" />, then a string <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234029.png" /> of length <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234030.png" /> is called a rank <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234032.png" /> configuration of the language <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234033.png" /> with resultant <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234034.png" />, where <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234035.png" />, if the following condition holds: If <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234036.png" /> can be substituted by <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234037.png" /> with respect to <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234038.png" /> and <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234039.png" />, if <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234040.png" /> and if <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234041.png" /> does not contain occurrances of configurations of ranks lower than <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234042.png" /> overlapping the considered <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234043.png" /> but not entirely contained in it, then <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234044.png" />. In English, the word combination  "continuous function"  can be regarded as a second rank configuration, the word  "function"  being the resultant (the word  "derivative" , for example, is also a resultant). It may be shown that, in a certain sense, a language is fully determined by the set of its configurations.
+
In the most fully developed analytic models of languages, the set of initial data is usually an object which models a set of grammatical sentences of a natural language, viz. some [[Formal language|formal language]] in a given alphabet (vocabulary) $  V $.  
 +
If $  L $
 +
is a language in the vocabulary $  V $
 +
and $  \forall u , v \in V  ^ {*}  [ uxv \in L \Rightarrow uyv \in L] $,  
 +
then one says that the string $  x $
 +
can be substituted by the string $  y $
 +
with respect to $  V $
 +
and $  L $;  
 +
if each one the strings $  x $
 +
and $  y $
 +
can be substituted by the other with respect to $  V $
 +
and $  L $,  
 +
then one says that $  x $
 +
and $  y $
 +
can be mutually substituted with respect to $  V $
 +
and $  L $.  
 +
The concept of mutual substitutability has a simple linguistic meaning: If $  L $
 +
is understood to be the set of grammatical sentences of some natural language, the mutually substitutable sets are  "syntactically equivalent"  (i.e. fulfilling the same syntactic functions) word combinations. In particular, if a single-symbol string a $(
 +
in linguistic interpretation: a word) is mutually substitutable with a string $  x $
 +
of length > 1 $,  
 +
$  x $
 +
is a  "potential constituent" , i.e. may be a constituent of the linguistically natural constituent structures of grammatical sentences of this language (cf. [[Syntactic structure|Syntactic structure]]); in such a case the string $  x $
 +
is called a first rank configuration of the language $  L $
 +
with resultant a $.  
 +
Thus, in the English language, the string  "uniformly continuous"  can be regarded as a first rank configuration with resultant  "continuous" . However, first rank configurations do not exhaust all  "potential constituents" ; for example, the word combination  "continuous function"  is not a first rank configuration, since only words such as  "function" ,  "derivative" , etc., can be substituted by it, but it cannot itself be substituted by any of these words ( "fx is a uniformly continuous function"  is a correct statement, but  "fx is a uniform function"  is not). Therefore one introduces the following definition: If $  r > 1 $
 +
is a natural number and if the concept of a rank $  i $
 +
configuration of the language $  L $
 +
has been defined for each $  i = 1 \dots r - 1 $,  
 +
then a string $  x $
 +
of length > 1 $
 +
is called a rank $  r $
 +
configuration of the language $  L $
 +
with resultant a $,  
 +
where a \in V $,  
 +
if the following condition holds: If a $
 +
can be substituted by $  x $
 +
with respect to $  V $
 +
and $  L $,  
 +
if $  z _ {1} x z _ {2} \in L $
 +
and if $  z _ {1} x z _ {2} $
 +
does not contain occurrances of configurations of ranks lower than $  r $
 +
overlapping the considered $  x $
 +
but not entirely contained in it, then $  z _ {1} a z _ {2} \in L $.  
 +
In English, the word combination  "continuous function"  can be regarded as a second rank configuration, the word  "function"  being the resultant (the word  "derivative" , for example, is also a resultant). It may be shown that, in a certain sense, a language is fully determined by the set of its configurations.
  
The configurational model belongs to the so-called syntagmatic analytic models of a language, which are intended to describe the relations between the elements of segments of speech (in linguistics such relations are called syntagmatic). Another class of analytic models of a language are paradigmatic models, intended to describe paradigmatic relations, i.e. relations between the elements of a language in its system. In such models the usual procedure is to construct certain relations on the vocabulary, which are often (but not always) equivalence relations. In particular, paradigmatic analytic models of a language serve to construct formal analogues of traditional linguistic categories such as parts of speech, case, gender, phoneme, etc. A set of grammatical sentences also serves as the  "starting material"  in many paradigmatic analytic models of a language; the concept of substitutability is employed in several models of this type. The simplest equivalence relation obtained in this way is the mutual substitutability relation on the vocabulary (i.e. on the set of all one-element strings); the equivalence classes induced by this relation are called families. If one introduces an additional relation on the vocabulary, consisting of  "to be different forms of the same word"  (more precisely, of one lexeme; this is, e.g., the relation between  "to limit"  and  "limiting"  or between  "number"  and  "numbers" ; it involves a certain idealization in that it is assumed that a word may be the form of one lexeme only; the respective equivalence classes are called neighbourhoods), then these two relations may be used to introduce certain other classifications, which may be regarded as approximations to the formal analogues of parts of speech and other traditional grammatical concepts, in particular the concepts of case and gender of nouns. These last two concepts are particularly intensively studied; a number of models based on the concept of grammaticality as well as other types of models have been suggested for their formalization. In one model, in particular, each case of nouns is treated as a set of  "uniformly directed"  forms of nouns, while each gender is treated as a set of  "uniformly directing"  nouns. The initial data in this model, which serve to determine the gender, are the vocabulary, the set of neighbourhoods, the set of nouns and the binary relation of  "potential subordination"  in the vocabulary: <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234045.png" /> potentially subordinates <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234046.png" /> if, in some  "linguistically natural"  dependency structure (cf. [[Syntactic structure|Syntactic structure]]) of a grammatical sentence in this language, some occurrence of <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234047.png" /> (immediately) depends on some occurrence of <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/a/a012/a012340/a01234048.png" />; additional initial data of the same nature are added to determine the gender. Models based on  "potential subordination"  or other concepts related to dependency structures apparently permit a better formalization of traditional grammatical categories than do models involving strings only, since in the former models syntactic and linear relations are separated (cf. [[Grammar, transformational|Grammar, transformational]]).
+
The configurational model belongs to the so-called syntagmatic analytic models of a language, which are intended to describe the relations between the elements of segments of speech (in linguistics such relations are called syntagmatic). Another class of analytic models of a language are paradigmatic models, intended to describe paradigmatic relations, i.e. relations between the elements of a language in its system. In such models the usual procedure is to construct certain relations on the vocabulary, which are often (but not always) equivalence relations. In particular, paradigmatic analytic models of a language serve to construct formal analogues of traditional linguistic categories such as parts of speech, case, gender, phoneme, etc. A set of grammatical sentences also serves as the  "starting material"  in many paradigmatic analytic models of a language; the concept of substitutability is employed in several models of this type. The simplest equivalence relation obtained in this way is the mutual substitutability relation on the vocabulary (i.e. on the set of all one-element strings); the equivalence classes induced by this relation are called families. If one introduces an additional relation on the vocabulary, consisting of  "to be different forms of the same word"  (more precisely, of one lexeme; this is, e.g., the relation between  "to limit"  and  "limiting"  or between  "number"  and  "numbers" ; it involves a certain idealization in that it is assumed that a word may be the form of one lexeme only; the respective equivalence classes are called neighbourhoods), then these two relations may be used to introduce certain other classifications, which may be regarded as approximations to the formal analogues of parts of speech and other traditional grammatical concepts, in particular the concepts of case and gender of nouns. These last two concepts are particularly intensively studied; a number of models based on the concept of grammaticality as well as other types of models have been suggested for their formalization. In one model, in particular, each case of nouns is treated as a set of  "uniformly directed"  forms of nouns, while each gender is treated as a set of  "uniformly directing"  nouns. The initial data in this model, which serve to determine the gender, are the vocabulary, the set of neighbourhoods, the set of nouns and the binary relation of  "potential subordination"  in the vocabulary: a $
 +
potentially subordinates $  b $
 +
if, in some  "linguistically natural"  dependency structure (cf. [[Syntactic structure|Syntactic structure]]) of a grammatical sentence in this language, some occurrence of $  b $(
 +
immediately) depends on some occurrence of a $;  
 +
additional initial data of the same nature are added to determine the gender. Models based on  "potential subordination"  or other concepts related to dependency structures apparently permit a better formalization of traditional grammatical categories than do models involving strings only, since in the former models syntactic and linear relations are separated (cf. [[Grammar, transformational|Grammar, transformational]]).
  
 
The mathematical apparatus employed in the construction of analytic models of a language is usually fairly simple. In some models it merely involves the simplest concepts of set theory (such models are frequently called set-theoretic, and this term is sometimes extended to cover all analytic models of a language). In other cases algebraic concepts are employed, in particular those of the theory of semi-groups and of the algebra of binary relations; this is why the theory of analytic models of a language is sometimes referred to as algebraic linguistics.
 
The mathematical apparatus employed in the construction of analytic models of a language is usually fairly simple. In some models it merely involves the simplest concepts of set theory (such models are frequently called set-theoretic, and this term is sometimes extended to cover all analytic models of a language). In other cases algebraic concepts are employed, in particular those of the theory of semi-groups and of the algebra of binary relations; this is why the theory of analytic models of a language is sometimes referred to as algebraic linguistics.

Latest revision as of 18:47, 5 April 2020


analyzing model of a language

A type of mathematical construction used in mathematical linguistics to describe the structure of natural languages. These constructions are used in the formal modelling of basic linguistic categories and of the process of linguistic research itself; in other words, certain sets of "disordered" data about the language (or, more exactly, about speech) are used to deduce certain information about the structural mechanism of the language, i.e. about its grammar in the wider sense of this word. The "functioning" of such a model does not always have the character of an effective construction, since the set of initial data need not be a constructive object; in principle, this does not render such models inferior.

In the most fully developed analytic models of languages, the set of initial data is usually an object which models a set of grammatical sentences of a natural language, viz. some formal language in a given alphabet (vocabulary) $ V $. If $ L $ is a language in the vocabulary $ V $ and $ \forall u , v \in V ^ {*} [ uxv \in L \Rightarrow uyv \in L] $, then one says that the string $ x $ can be substituted by the string $ y $ with respect to $ V $ and $ L $; if each one the strings $ x $ and $ y $ can be substituted by the other with respect to $ V $ and $ L $, then one says that $ x $ and $ y $ can be mutually substituted with respect to $ V $ and $ L $. The concept of mutual substitutability has a simple linguistic meaning: If $ L $ is understood to be the set of grammatical sentences of some natural language, the mutually substitutable sets are "syntactically equivalent" (i.e. fulfilling the same syntactic functions) word combinations. In particular, if a single-symbol string $ a $( in linguistic interpretation: a word) is mutually substitutable with a string $ x $ of length $ > 1 $, $ x $ is a "potential constituent" , i.e. may be a constituent of the linguistically natural constituent structures of grammatical sentences of this language (cf. Syntactic structure); in such a case the string $ x $ is called a first rank configuration of the language $ L $ with resultant $ a $. Thus, in the English language, the string "uniformly continuous" can be regarded as a first rank configuration with resultant "continuous" . However, first rank configurations do not exhaust all "potential constituents" ; for example, the word combination "continuous function" is not a first rank configuration, since only words such as "function" , "derivative" , etc., can be substituted by it, but it cannot itself be substituted by any of these words ( "fx is a uniformly continuous function" is a correct statement, but "fx is a uniform function" is not). Therefore one introduces the following definition: If $ r > 1 $ is a natural number and if the concept of a rank $ i $ configuration of the language $ L $ has been defined for each $ i = 1 \dots r - 1 $, then a string $ x $ of length $ > 1 $ is called a rank $ r $ configuration of the language $ L $ with resultant $ a $, where $ a \in V $, if the following condition holds: If $ a $ can be substituted by $ x $ with respect to $ V $ and $ L $, if $ z _ {1} x z _ {2} \in L $ and if $ z _ {1} x z _ {2} $ does not contain occurrances of configurations of ranks lower than $ r $ overlapping the considered $ x $ but not entirely contained in it, then $ z _ {1} a z _ {2} \in L $. In English, the word combination "continuous function" can be regarded as a second rank configuration, the word "function" being the resultant (the word "derivative" , for example, is also a resultant). It may be shown that, in a certain sense, a language is fully determined by the set of its configurations.

The configurational model belongs to the so-called syntagmatic analytic models of a language, which are intended to describe the relations between the elements of segments of speech (in linguistics such relations are called syntagmatic). Another class of analytic models of a language are paradigmatic models, intended to describe paradigmatic relations, i.e. relations between the elements of a language in its system. In such models the usual procedure is to construct certain relations on the vocabulary, which are often (but not always) equivalence relations. In particular, paradigmatic analytic models of a language serve to construct formal analogues of traditional linguistic categories such as parts of speech, case, gender, phoneme, etc. A set of grammatical sentences also serves as the "starting material" in many paradigmatic analytic models of a language; the concept of substitutability is employed in several models of this type. The simplest equivalence relation obtained in this way is the mutual substitutability relation on the vocabulary (i.e. on the set of all one-element strings); the equivalence classes induced by this relation are called families. If one introduces an additional relation on the vocabulary, consisting of "to be different forms of the same word" (more precisely, of one lexeme; this is, e.g., the relation between "to limit" and "limiting" or between "number" and "numbers" ; it involves a certain idealization in that it is assumed that a word may be the form of one lexeme only; the respective equivalence classes are called neighbourhoods), then these two relations may be used to introduce certain other classifications, which may be regarded as approximations to the formal analogues of parts of speech and other traditional grammatical concepts, in particular the concepts of case and gender of nouns. These last two concepts are particularly intensively studied; a number of models based on the concept of grammaticality as well as other types of models have been suggested for their formalization. In one model, in particular, each case of nouns is treated as a set of "uniformly directed" forms of nouns, while each gender is treated as a set of "uniformly directing" nouns. The initial data in this model, which serve to determine the gender, are the vocabulary, the set of neighbourhoods, the set of nouns and the binary relation of "potential subordination" in the vocabulary: $ a $ potentially subordinates $ b $ if, in some "linguistically natural" dependency structure (cf. Syntactic structure) of a grammatical sentence in this language, some occurrence of $ b $( immediately) depends on some occurrence of $ a $; additional initial data of the same nature are added to determine the gender. Models based on "potential subordination" or other concepts related to dependency structures apparently permit a better formalization of traditional grammatical categories than do models involving strings only, since in the former models syntactic and linear relations are separated (cf. Grammar, transformational).

The mathematical apparatus employed in the construction of analytic models of a language is usually fairly simple. In some models it merely involves the simplest concepts of set theory (such models are frequently called set-theoretic, and this term is sometimes extended to cover all analytic models of a language). In other cases algebraic concepts are employed, in particular those of the theory of semi-groups and of the algebra of binary relations; this is why the theory of analytic models of a language is sometimes referred to as algebraic linguistics.

References

[1] O.S. Kulagina, "On a means of defining grammatical concepts on the base of set theory" Problemy Kibernet. , 1 (1958) pp. 203–214 (In Russian)
[2] V.A. Uspenskii, "On the Kolmogorov definition of case" Byull. Obshch. Problemy Mashinnogo Perevoda : 5 (1957) pp. 11–18 (In Russian)
[3] V.A. Uspenskii, "A model for the concept of phoneme" Voprosy Yazykoznaniya : 6 (1964) pp. 39–53 (In Russian)
[4] S. Markus, "Algebraic linguistics: analytical models" , Acad. Press (1967)
[5] I.I. Revzin, "Modelling and typologizing Slavic languages" , Moscow (1967) (In Russian)
[6] A.V. [A.V. Gladkii] Gladkij, I.A. [I.A. Mel'chuk] Mel'Avcuk, "Elements of mathematical linguistics" , Mouton (1983)
[7] A.V. Gladkii, "Formal grammars and languages" , Moscow (1973) (In Russian)
How to Cite This Entry:
Analytic model of a language. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Analytic_model_of_a_language&oldid=45177
This article was adapted from an original article by A.V. Gladkii (originator), which appeared in Encyclopedia of Mathematics - ISBN 1402006098. See original article